FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE*
SALLY S. SIMPSON
University of Maryland
Feminist research has expanded beyond its origins in Women’s Studies
to influence the more traditionally bounded academic disciplines. Criminology
has not been immune to these excursions. This paper presents an
overview of feminist theory/methods and its applications within select
areas of crime and justice studies. Points of intra-theoretical divergence as
well as directions for future feminist contributions are noted.
“WHY CAN’T A WOMAN BE MORE LIKE A MAN?”
One is tempted to respond to Henry Higgins’s familiar lament with a cynical
observation: criminological theory assumes a woman is like a man. As
many feminist-criminologists have noted (early critics include Heidensohn,
1968; Klein, 1973; and Smart, 1976), most middle-range and macro theories
of crime generously assume that what is true for the gander is true for the
goose (see also Harris, 1977). As tempting as this simple assertion might be,
however, a closer inspection reveals a more complicated picture.
Some feminist critics (Daly and Chesney-Lind, 1988) suggest that criminology,
like other social sciences, is androcentric, that is, study of crime and the
justice process is shaped by male experiences and understandings of the social
world. Such studiedrealities form the core of “general” theories of crime/
deviance without taking female experience, as crime participant or victim,
into account:
[Men] create the world from their own point of view, which then
becomes the truth to be described . . . Power to create the world from
one’s point of view is power in its male form (MacKinnon, 1982:23).
Not all criminological research has ignored women, but all too often, pre-
1970s research on female offenders and victims of crime fell prey to unreflecting
sexism and, in its more extreme form, misogyny. Females who deviated
from expected roles were viewed as morally corrupt, hysterical, diseased,
manipulative, and devious (Glueck and Glueck, 1934). Law-violating and
-conforming behaviors were believed to stem from the same etiological
source-the female nature (Edwards, 1985; Klein, 1973).1 A woman, it
* My thanks to Kathleen Daly, Nicole Hahn Rafter, and N. Craig Smith for their
insightful comments on a draft of this paper. I was assisted in my revisions by the
criticisms of three anonymous reviewers. All of the above are to be commended for their
assistance, but none is responsible for the ideas and arguments contained herein.
1. This is not to suggest that biological reductionism is absent in studiedtheories of
male criminality. Such explanations of male crime abound (e.g., Wilson and Herrnstein,
1985). However, with the demise of phrenology, social factors replaced biology as key
CRIMINOLOGY VOLUME2 7 NUMBER4 1989 605
606 SIMPSON
seemed-whether good or bad-could never be like a man.
These observations are not new, but they reflect a different voice, a feminist
voice, that has been added to the criminological discourse. The purpose of
this review essay is to introduce feminist criminology and its intellectual parent,
feminism, to the uninitiated reader. It would be presumptuous to suggest
that all relevant studies and arguments about gender and crime are included
here. Such an extensive review is more appropriate for a book, and depending
on the topic, it has likely already been done and done well (e.g., Eaton,
1986; Freedman, 1981; Heidensohn, 1985; Mann, 1984; Naffine, 1988; Smart,
1976). Instead, illustrative examples of different types of feminist thinking
are presented to show how feminism has reframed our points of reference,
underlying assumptions, and understandings about crime, victimization, and
the justice process.
To achieve these aims, the paper is organized into three sections. First, the
perspectives and methods that constitute feminist analysis are sorted and differentiated.
Second, three areas of criminological study (the female offender,
female victim, and criminal justice processing) are discussed because they are
key areas in which feminist approaches have been incorporated. Third, directions
for further integration are suggested.
FEMINISM: PERSPECTIVES AND METHODS
Feminism is best understood as both a world view and a social movement
that encompasses assumptions and beliefs about the origins and consequences
of gendered social organization as well as strategic directions and actions for
social change. As such, feminism is both analytical and empirical. In its
incipient form, feminist research almost exclusively focused on women-as a
way of placing women at the center of inquiry and building a base of knowledge.
As it has matured, feminism has become more encompassing, taking
into account the gendered understanding of all aspects of human culture and
relationships (Stacey and Thorne, 1985:305).
It would be a mistake, however, to think of feminism as a single theory.
Feminism has expanded into a diverse set of perspectives and agendas, each
based on different definitions of the “problem,” competing conceptions of the
origins and mechanisms of gender inequality/oppression, and divergent strategies
for its eradication. Collectively, these perspectives share a concern with
identifying and representing women’s interests, interests judged to be insufficiently
represented and accommodated within the mainstream (Oakley,
1981:335).
etiological forces. These explanations have not been seriously challenged. Conversely,
until the feminist critique of the 197Os, biogenic/psychogenic models of female crime went,
for the most part, unchallenged.
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 607
LIBERAL FEMINISM
Liberal feminism was conceived within a liberal-bourgeois tradition that
called for women’s equality of opportunity and freedom of choice (Eisenstein,
1981). For the most part, liberal feminists see gender inequality2 emerging
from the creation of separate and distinct spheres of influence and traditional
attitudes about the appropriate role of men and women in society (Pateman,
1987). Such attitudes are reinforced by discrimination against women in education,
the work place, politics, and other public arenas.
Liberals do not believe the system to be inherently unequal; discrimination
is not systemic. Rather, men and women can work together to “androgynize”
gender roles (i.e., blend male and female traits and characteristics;
Bem, 1974) and eliminate outdated policies and practices that discriminate
against women. Affirmative action, the equal rights amendment, and other
equal opportunity laws/policies are advocated as redistributive measures
until a meritocratic gender restructuring of society occurs.
SOCIALIST FEMINISM
For socialists, gender oppression is an obvious feature of capitalist societies.
Depending on whether one is a socialist woman (Marxist-feminist) or a
socialist-feminist, however, the weight that one gives to capitalism as a necessary
and/or sufficient cause of that oppression will vary (Eisenstein, 1979). If
one is the former, gender (and race) oppression is seen as secondary to and
reflective of class oppression.
Socialist-feminists attempt a synthesis between two systems of domination,
class and patriarchy (male supremacy). Both relations of production and
reproduction are structured by capitalist patriarchy (Beauvoir, 1960; Hartmann,
1979; Mitchell, 197 1). Gender. difference, as a defining characteristic
of power and privilege in a capitalist society can only be attacked by constructing
a completely different society, one that is free of gender and class
stratification (Oakley, 1981).
RADICAL FEMINISM
The origins of patriarchy, and the subordination of women therein, are
seen by radical feminists to rest in male aggression and control of women’s
sexuality. Men are inherently more aggressive than women, who, because of
Phillips (1987) argues that the choice of terms describing gender relations imply
particular views of what the problem is. So, inequality (a term favored by liberals and some
women of color) suggests that women deserve what men and/or whites are granted.
Oppression (socialists and women of color) implies a complex combination of forces (ideological,
political, and economic) that keep woman in her place. Subordination is a term
favored by radical feminists and some women of color who identify the holder of power as
the culprit (men and whites respectively).
2.
608 SIMPSON
their relative size disadvantages and dependency on men during child-bearing
years, are easy to dominate and control. The arguments of radical feminists
(e.g., Atkinson, 1974; Barry, 1979; Firestone, 1970; Rich, 1980) bring sexuality
to the analytical fore. The “personal” is “political” (Millett, 1971). Sex
not gender is the crucial analytical category; male domination, not class, is
the fundamental origin of female subordination. Radical feminists’ political
and social agendas encompass lesbian separatism (Atkinson, 1984) and technological
control of reproduction (Firestone, 1970).
WOMEN OF COLOR
In her eloquent “Ain’t I a woman” speech, Sojourner Truth (1851)
informed white suffragists of their myopia about race by highlighting how as
a black woman her experience was different from theirs. Joseph and Lewis
(1981) remind us that Truth’s commentary is no less relevant today. Many
women of color see the women’s liberation movement as hopelessly white and
middle class, immune to their concerns. As Hooks (1987:62) observed,
Most people in the United States think of feminism . . . as a movement
that aims to make women the social equals of men. . . . Since men are
not equals in white supremacist, capitalist, patriarchal class structure,
which men do women want to be equal to?
The alternative frameworks developed by women of color heighten feminism’s
sensitivity to the complex interplay of gender, class, and race oppression.
Patriarchy permeates the lives of minority women, but it does not take
the same form that it does for whites (Brittan and Maynard, 1984). Though
these contributions may not have coalesced yet into a coherent theoretical
framework (at least according to Jagger and Rothenberg, 1984), radical
(Lorde, 1988), socialist (Mullins, 1986), and Marxist (Davis, 1981) women of
color have provided possible points of integration with theories of race
oppression (e.g., Joseph, 1981a, 1981b; Wellman, 1977).
In sum, feminist theory is not one perspective; it is a cacophony of comment
and criticism “concerned with demystifying masculine knowledge as
objective knowledge” (Brittan and Maynard, 1984:2 10) and offering insights
from a women’s perspective.
FEMINIST METHODS
The male epistemological stance, which corresponds to the world it creates,
is objectivity; the ostensibly uninvolved stance, the view from a distance
and from no particular perspective, apparently transparent to its
reality. It does not comprehend its own perspectivity, does not recognize
what it sees as subject like itself, or that the way it apprehends its world
is a form of its subjection and presupposes it (MacKinnon (1982:23-24).
Concern over the nonobjective consequences of so-called objective normal
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 609
science (Kuhn, 1970) has led some feminists to challenge the scientific enterprise.
Keller (1982) arranges these challenges on a political spectrum from
slightly left of center (liberal feminists) to the more radical left. The liberal
critique takes an equal employment opportunity approach by observing the
relative absence of women from the scientific community. This view “in no
way conflicts either with traditional conceptions of science or with current
liberal, egalitarian politics” (p. 114).
From this point, however, the criticisms become increasingly fundamental
to the way knowledge is produced; they range from charges of bias in selecting
research topics and interpreting results to rejecting rationality and objectivity
as purely male products. More radical feminists have adopted a
methodological strategy that is in direct opposition to the scientific method.
In order to “see” women’s existence (which has been invisible to objective
scientific methods) “feminist women must deliberately and courageously integrate
. . . their own experiences of oppression and discrimination . . . into the
research process” (Miles, 1983: 12 1). Feminist methods are necessarily subjectivist,
transdisciplinary, nonhierarchical, and empowering.
Where one falls along Keller’s feminist-political spectrum will determine
one’s choice of methods (i.e., quantitative versus qualitative) and whether one
sees methods and theory as interrelated as opposed to separate and distinct.
Thus, methods used by feminists are more diverse than typically credited (for
examples, see Jayarate, 1983; Reinhartz, 1983; Stacey and Thorne, 1985).
Together, the above theoretical and methodological points form a feminist
perspective. All have been incorporated into criminology, but some have had
a greater impact than others. The goal in the next section is to identify the
ways in which these approaches and methods have changed the way criminologists
address the problems of crime and justice.
INCORPORATING THE FRAMEWORKS
THE FEMALE OFFENDER
The stirrings of feminist criminology are nearly two decades old. Heidensohn
(1968: 17 l), in a “pre-feminist” paper, bemoaned the state of knowledge
about female deviance and called for a “crash programme of research which
telescopes decades of comparable studies of males.” Later, Klein (1973) and
Smart (1976) were to bring explicitly feminist perspectives to their critiques
of extant theoretical and empirical work on the female offender. Klein, a
Marxist-feminist, noted the absence of economic and other social explanations
for female crime. Smart, working within more of a radical feminist perspective,
stressed the linkages among sexist theory, patriarchy, and sexism in
practice-specifically identifying the relationship between stereotypical
assumptions about the causes of female crime and how female offenders are
controlled and treated.
610 SIMPSON
Both Klein and Smart set an agenda for a new feminist criminology, but
their more radical approaches were derailed by the publication of Simon’s
Women and Crime and F. Adler’s Sisters in Crime (1975). Claiming that a
“new” female offender was emerging (white collar and/or male like), Simon
and Adler generated tremendous interest in female crime (a clear aim of
incipient feminism). But, tying the female offender’s emergence to women’s
liberation brought about a “moral panic” (Smart, 1976), which was viewed by
some as a blacklash to the women’s movement.3 In Chesney-Lind’s (1980:29)
words, it represented “another in a century long series of symbolic attempts
to keep women subordinate to men by threatening those who aspire for equality
with the images of the witch, the bitch, and the whore.”4
As with many social problems of our day, female crime became interesting
only when it transcended the expected boundaries of class, race, and gender.
As a “quasi-theory,” the liberation-crime relationship had great appeal for
nonfeminist crimino1ogists.s But tests of the thesis were less than supportive.
In fact most discredited it (Austin, 1982; Giordano et al., 1981), and others
found evidence of a link between female crime and economic marginalization
(Datesman and Scarpitti, 1980; Gora, 1982; Mukherjee and Fitzgerald, 198 1;
Steffensmeier, 1978, 1981; Steffensmeier and Cobb, 1981). The new female
offender identified by Simon and Adler was more myth than reality (Steffensmeier,
1978). These conclusions did not differ substantially from Klein’s
(1973), yet they came years after her original critique-a fact that dramatically
illustrates the marginality of feminist criminology at the time. Yet, subsequent
research on the causes of female crime has clearly buttressed the
economic/class perspectives of Marxist/socialist feminists as well as the
3. The links between women’s liberation and changing patterns of female criminality
were made before. Bishop (1931) complained that women’s liberation during the 1920s had
three negative results: ( I ) more women were turning criminal; (2) a “better” class of
women were becoming criminal more often; and (3) women were becoming sexually criminal
at a younger age (cited in Rasche, 1974).
To be fair, both Simon and Adler had more to offer than mere speculation about
the “dark side” of women’s liberation. Simon’s research documents the basic inequities
between male and female correctional facilities and treatments. By attributing these differences
to male chivalry toward women, she takes a liberal feminist approach to the problem
of gender and justice, an approach that heavily influenced later works in this area. Adler’s
work, while more impressionistic than Simon’s, attempted to explain differences in crime
rates between white and black females. Although her interpretations gave rise to more
systematic examinations of intra-gender race differences in crime that are highly critical of
her interpretations and methods, the issues she raised are of primary importance to most
feminist criminologists today.
A research focus on gender alone does not qualify one as a feminist just as a focus
on class does not make one a marxist. Rather, as part of their endeavor, feminist criminologists
must seriously consider the nature of gender relations and the peculiar brand of
oppression that patriarchal relations bring (Leonard, 1982).
4.
5.
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 61 1
“opportunity” perspectives of the liberal feminists (Ageton, 1983; Box, 1983;
Box and Hale, 1984; Elliott and Ageton, 1980; Giordano et al., 1981).
In retrospect, feminist criminology both gained and lost from the narrow
focus on liberation and crime. On the plus side, we gained a better insight
into the historical (Mukherjee and Fitzgerald, 198 1) and cross-cultural (F.
Adler, 1981; Plenska, 1980) patterns of female crime. But because the liberation
thesis was so limited, it diverted attention from the material and structural
forces that shape women’s lives and experiences. It is in these areas that
women of color and socialist and radical feminist criminologists are more apt
to focus etiological attention (Hagan et al., 1985, 1987; Lewis, 1981; Miller,
1985; Rafter and Natalizia, 1981; Wilson, 1985).
WOMEN VICTIMS: THE RADICAL FEMINIST CRITIQUE
Liberal feminism has dominated studies of the female offender, but the
same is not true of victimology (Daly and Chesney-Lind, 1988). Shifting
away from analyses that blame the victim for her victimization (Amir,
1967),6 radical feminists have constructed alternative interpretations of
offender-victim relationships and victim experiences of criminal justice
(Chapman and Gates, 1978; Klein, 1981; Wood, 1981).
Brownmiller’s (1975) historical and cross-cultural study of rape brought a
radical feminist perspective to the center of public consciousness. Building
on the argument that rape is not a crime of sex but rather an act of power and
dominance (Greer, 1970), Brownmiller concluded that rape is a tool in the
arsenal of all men to control all women.
Radical feminists have reframed the ways in which rape is commonly
understood in our society. Rather than a crime of sex, it is more apt to be
viewed as one of male power, control, and domination. Brownmiller’s work,
coupled with that of other radical feminists (e.g., Griffin, 1979; Riger and
Gordon, 1981), opened a floodgate of inquiry into rape and other types of
victimizations that are “uniquely feminine” (Wilson, 1985:4), such as pornography
(Dworkin, 1981), battering (Dobash and Dobash, 1979; Martin, 1976;
Straus et al., 1980), incest (Finkelhor, 1979; Moyer, 1985; Stanko, 1985) and
sexual harassment (MacKinnon, 1979; Stanko, 1985).
Guiding much of this research is the radical feminist critique of official
conceptions and definitions of violence, which are viewed as male centered
and incapable of incorporating the full range of female experiences of violence
(i.e., from intimidation and coercion to physical violence and death). A
woman-centered definition of violence is one that portrays violence as a form
6. Precipitous behavior has ranged from dressing provacatively, saying no to sex
while “meaning” yes, “nagging” a spouse, Lolita-like seductiveness on the part of the victim,
and so on.
612 SIMPSON
of social domination rather than a random and/or noninstrumental form of
expression (Hanmer, 1981:32).
Radical feminists have dominated but not monopolized feminist perspectives
in this area. Socialist feminists, liberals, and women of color have also
participated in the dialogue. Gordon’s (1988) research of family violence is
implicitly critical of some radical feminists’ overly deterministic conception
of patriarchy. Such an image, she argues, denies agency to women and cannot
incorporate “the chronic conflict, unpredictability, and ambivalent emotions
that have characterized relations between the sexes” (xi-xii).
In another historical study, Tomes (1 978) links variations in spousal abuse
to changes in the economic position of the working class generally and the
male’s position within the family specifically. As the working class improved
its economic position and males cemented greater power within their families,
the official incidence of working-class battering decreased.
Based on her findings, Tomes argues that feminists may need to reconceptualize
the relationship among male power, female economic dependency,
and battering. Dependency is not necessarily tied to greater abuse; in fact,
the opposite may be true. A wife’s economic independence may exert a
greater challenge to male authority within the family, thus creating a climate
in which husbands resort to battering as a means to reestablish their control.
Studies that find great variety in the cross-cultural prevalence and incidence
of rape and battering (e.g., Pagelow, 1981; Sanday, 1981) have forced
feminists to examine patriarchal relations across different societal and situational
arrangements (e.g., Wilson, 1985). If female victimization is a function
of changing the needs of a capitalist/patriarchal system, then male domination
and its relationship to female victimization need not be viewed as inevitable
or immutable.
Around the themes of rape and control of sexuality, patriarchy and racism
marry and divorce in intricate ways (Davis, 1981). In the United States,
white racism and fear gave rise to mythological constructions of black sexuality.
Black males are perceived as sexual threats and have been hunted and
hanged for their “rape potential.” For black victims of rape, the justice process
is not simply gendered-it is racially gendered. Data indicate that blackon-
black rapes are not taken as seriously by authorities as those that involve
white victims (Kleck, 1981; LaFree, 1980). Such findings have led one prominent
black scholar (Joseph, 1981b:27) to comment, “It must be considered
an impossibility for white men to rape Black women in the eyes of justice and
in the minds of many. Black women apparently are considered as something
other than ‘women.’ ”
GENDER AND JUSTICE PROCESSING
A final area to be discussed in this literature review is gendered justice.
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 613
Comedian Richard Pryor once called attention to discrimination in the U.S.
criminal justice system by defining justice as “just us.” His concern with
differential sentencing practices is one shared by feminists who primarily
study the conditions under which criminal justice is gendered and with what
consequences. Although liberal approaches typically dominate the genderand-
justice research, other feminist perspectives are gaining ground-specially
in research on courts and corrections.
There are many stages in the criminal justice system at which gender may
have an impact on decision making. The findings of some of the betterknown
studies of several strategic points in the decision-making process are
summarized below.
POLICE
Arguments about whether and how justice is gendered must begin with
police behavior. That police decisions to arrest can be influenced by extralegal
factors such as the demeanor of the offender (Black, 1980), has been
established. It is less clear how gender, either alone or in conjunction with
other characteristics, may consciously or inadvertently influence police
behavior.
In the liberal “equal treatment” tradition, Moyer and White (1981) test
police bias in response decisions under “probable” responses to hypothetical
situations. Neither gender nor race had an effect on police behavior once
crime type, especially as it interacts with demeanor of the offender, was controlled.
On the other hand, Freyerhern’s (1981) comparison of juvenile male
and female probabilities of transition from self-report incident to police contact
and arrest, finds males to be more likely to incur police contact and arrest
than females. Both of these studies are methodologically problematic, however.
Moyer and White cannot generalize their findings to real police
encounters and Freyerhern (198 1 :90) does not calculate transition probabilities
across individual offense categories, nor does he include status offenses.
Avoiding some of these methodological traps but still working within a liberal
tradition, Visher (1983) finds the interaction between race and gender to
be a key factor influencing arrest decision. Visher finds police chivalry only
toward white females once “legal” factors are controlled. She hypothesizes
that black females are treated more harshly than their white counterparts
because they are less apt to display expected (i.e., traditional) gender behaviors
and characteristics when they encounter a mostly white and male police
force.
Race and gender are also found to interact through victim characteristics
(Smith et al.. 1984). An analysis of 272 police-citizen encounters, in which
both a suspected offender and victim were present, revealed that white female
victims received more preferential treatment from police than black female
614 SIMPSON
victims. Thus, although chivalry may be alive and well for white women, it
appears to be dead (if it ever existed) for blacks.
COURTS
Police contact is not the only point in justice processing at which discrimination
can occur. Women have been found to receive more lenient treatment
in the early stages of court processing (i.e., bail, release on own recognizance,
and/or cash alternatives to bail; I. Nagel, 1983) and further into the process,
e.g., conviction and sentencing (Bernstein et al., 1977; S. Nagel and Weitzman,
1972; Simon, 1975). Other studies find no gender bias when controlling
for crime seriousness and prior record (Farrington and Morris, 1983) or little
effect from extralegal factors when legal factors and bench bias are controlled
(I. Nagel, 1983). Variation in sentencing may be related to so-called countertype
offenses, that is, women are treated more harshly when processed for
nontraditional female crimes, like assault (Bernstein et al., 1977; S. Nagel and
Weitzman, 1972), or when they violate female sexual norms (Chesney-Lind,
1973; Schlossman and Wallach, 1978). Given variable-specification
problems, however, some of these findings are potentially spurious.
Once again, race may confound these effects. Spohn et al. (1982) address
the issue of paternalism in sentencing, especially for black women. Controlling
for prior record and attorney type, they found that black women are
incarcerated significantly less often than black men, but about as often as
white men. They conclude that the apparently lenient treatment of black
women is not due to paternalism in their favor but rather to the racial discrimination
against black vis-a-vis white men.
Studies of court processing are not entirely dominated by liberal perspectives.
More critical perspectives emphasize social power and patriarchal control
as the primary mechanisms through which justice is gendered
(Kruttschnitt, 1982, 1984). Eaton (1986:35) argues that magistrate courts in
Great Britain (the lower courts) reinforce the dominant imagery of justice
(i.e., courts are ostensibly fair and just) while they maintain the status quo:
“It is in these courts that the formal rules of society-the laws-are endorsed;
it is here, too, that the informal, unwritten rules regulating social relations
[e.g., gender, class, and race] are re-enacted.’’
When are females apt to be subjected to formal mechanisms of control?
When other, more informal, constraints are lacking or disrupted.
Kruttschnitt (1982, 1984) suggests that sentencing outcomes are affected by a
woman’s social status and/or her respectability. Differential sentencing
among women is tied to the degree to which women are subjected to formal
versus informal social control in their everyday lives.
Daly (1987a, 1989b) and Eaton (1986, 1987) offer convincing evidence that
the most important factor determining sentence outcome, once prior record
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 615
and offense seriousness are controlled, is marital and/or familial status.’
Marital status.has been found to matter for women (married receive more
lenient sentences) but not for men (Farrington and Morris, 1983; I. Nagel,
1981) or to be as important for both (Daly, 1987a, 1987b).
Pretrial release and sentencing are seen to be both “familied” and
“gendered.” They are familied in that court decisions regarding the removal
of men and women from families “elicit different concerns from the court”
(Daly 1987a:154). They are gendered in that women’s care of others and
male economic support for families represent “different types of dependencies
in family life” (p. 154). Men and women without family responsibilities are
treated similarly, but more harshly than familied men and women. Women
with families, however, are treated with the greatest degree of leniency due to
“the differing social costs arising from separating them from their families”
(Daly, 1987b3287). The economic role played by familied men can, more easily,
be covered by state entitlement programs, but it is putatively more difficult
to replace the functional role of familied women. Judges rationalize such
sentencing disparities as necessary for keeping families together (Daly,
1989b).
As these latter studies suggest, much of the observed gender bias in
processing may not be a case of overt discrimination for or against women
relative to men. Instead, judicial decisions may be influenced by broader societal
concerns about protecting nuclear families (Daly, 1989b) and the differing
roles and responsibilities contained therein (Eaton, 1986). It is not clear
that such forms of justice are overtly paternalistic, nor are they necessarily
racist. Rather, in a society that stratifies other rights and privileges by gender,
race, and class, “equality” in sentencing may not be just (Daly, 1989a).
Eaton (1986: 10-1 1) takes a somewhat different view of familied justice. In
her opinion, the courts reflect the needs and interests of patriarchy and capitalism,
in which attendant inequities are reproduced. “Family-based” justice
is a visible manifestation of the patriarchal and capitalist need to maintain
and protect the nuclear family-within which gender and productive/reproductive
relations first emerge.
CORRECTIONS
As it became clear that, compared with males, female prisoners were
treated differently (in some cases more leniently and in others more harshly),
liberal feminist perspectives came to dominate research questions and policy
considerations (see, Haft, 1980; Heide, 1974; Simon, 1975).
The linkages between female incarceration and male control of female sexuality
are developed by radical feminists (Chesney-Lind, 1973; Smart, 1976).
Rasche (1 974), for example, describes how prostitutes with venereal disease
7. These effects appear to be strongest for black defendants (Daly, 1989a).
616 SIMPSON
were prosecuted and institutionalized, with the “cure” as a condition of
release. Nondiseased prostitutes were less likely to go to jail or prison. Certain
prison practices, such as checking for evidence of a hymen during forced
physical examinations and vaginal contraband searches, have been used as
techniques to control the sexuality of youthful offenders and to humiliate and
degrade female inmates (Burkhart, 1973; Chesney-Lind, 1986).
Socialist feminists emphasize how prison tenure and treatment vary by
class and race (Freedman, 1981; French, 1977, 1978; Lewis, 1981; Rafter,
1985). In her historical accounting of the development of women’s prisons,
Rafter (1985155) observes how race determined whether and where a woman
was sent to prison.
Comparison of incarceration rates and in-prison treatment of black
women and white women demonstrates that partiality was extended
mainly to whites. Chivalry filtered them out of the prison system, helping
to create the even greater racial imbalances among female than male
prisoner populations. And partiality toward whites contributed to the
development of a bifurcated system, one track custodial and predominantly
black, the other reformatory and reserved mainly for whites.
The bifurcated system of women’s corrections emerges in part from two
competing images of female nature. In one view, women are seen as fragile
and immature creatures, more childlike than adult. Consequently, the female
offender is perceived as a “fallen woman,” in need of guidance but not a true
danger to society (Rasche, 1974). The reformatory is perfectly suited to such
an offender. Primarily staffed by reform-minded middle-class women,
reformatory training programs emphasized skills that would turn the white,
working-class misdemeanants into proper (and class-appropriate) women,
that is, good servants or wives (Rafter, 1985:82).
In custodial prisons, however, a different archetype dominated. Women’s
“dark side,” their inherent evil and immorality (Smart, 1976) shaped prison
philosophy. Here, the predominantly black felons (who were perceived as
more masculine, more self-centered, volatile, and dangerous) were treated
like men-only, given the conditions of their incarceration (i.e., fewness of
numbers and at the mercy of violent male offenders), their equality was tantamount
to brutal treatment and often death (Rafter, 1985:181).
The degree to which prisons function as something other than just places of
punishment and/or treatment is a popular theme in neo-Marxist literature.
Extending this interpretation to women, Marxist-feminists (e.g., Wilson,
1985; Hartz-Karp, 1981) argue that prisons, like other institutions of social
control (e.g., mental health facilities), retool deviant women for genderappropriate
roles in capitalist patriarchal societies:
If deviant women are more frequently assigned to the mental health system
for social control than to the criminal justice system, it is perhaps
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 617
because of the superior ability of the mental health system to “re-tool”
worn-out or rebellious domestic workers. (Wilson, 1985: 18)
Societal control of female deviance serves the needs of capital. When those
needs change, so too will the mechanisms and directions of social control.8
In this vein, Carlen (1983) demonstrates how “down, out and disordered”
women in Scotland are disciplined through medical and judicial apparatuses.
Most of the imprisoned are poor women; many have histories of alcohol and
drug abuse, and a large number come from violent homes. These life experiences
combine, setting into motion a cycle of deviance, imprisonment, and
patriarchal and class discipline that is tenacious and defeating:
Being seen as neither wholly mad nor wholly bad, [women] are treated to
a disciplinary regime where they are actually infantalised at the same
time as attempts are made to make them feel guilty about their double,
triple, quadruple, or even quintuple refusal of family, work, gender,
health, and reason (Carlen, 1983:209).
WHERE TO GO FROM HERE?
In 1976, Carol Smart suggested a number of topics for feminist research.9
A decade later, feminist criminology has amassed a considerable body of
knowledge in most of these areas-so much so in fact that feminists now are
more self-critical-especially in the areas of policy and legislative changes
(see Daly and Chesney-Lind, 1988). This is a positive step. It suggests not
only that a feminist voice is being heard, but that it is loud enough to produce
disagreement and intellectual exchange. Nonetheless, certain areas in criminology
either have been underexposed or are resistant to feminist concerns.
Thus, some new directions for feminist criminology are discussed below.10
RACE AND CRIME
Poorly conceived offender self-report surveys provided criminologists with
the empirical justification to ignore the race-crime relationship, and the prevailing
political climate reinforced our myopia. There is enormous risk in
ignoring that relationship, however. First, based on more sophisticated crime
Cloward and Piven (1979) and Box (1983) assert that female deviance is handled
by the medical community, in part, because women are more likely to direct their deviance
inward (i.e., they privatize it into self-destructive behaviors, like depression and suicide).
Such behavior is conceptualized as sickness (like “hysteria” earlier) and is thus subject to
the formal control of the psychiatric community.
The relevant topics are the female offender and the attitudes of criminal justice
personnel toward her; criminal justice processing; gender and corrections; and the structure
and purpose of law.
To suggest that feminists need to identify areas “appropriate” for feminist critique
implies that knowledge, as currently constructed, is selectively androcentric. I would argue
that criminology as a whole, like other academic disciplines, needs a feminist “overhaul.”
8.
9.
10.
618 SIMPSON
measures (e.g., National Youth Survey, National Crime Survey, cohort studies),
it is clear that the race-crime relationship is an essential one. Second,
and not unlike the gender-crime relationship, such reticence leaves the interpretive
door open to less critical perspectives.
Feminist criminologists have great potential in this area, but the data are
sparse and problematic and the analytic contributions few. Too often we rely
on quantitative studies that dichotomize race into white and black, or the
nonwhite category is broadened to include groups other than blacks (see, e.g.,
Tracy et al., in press). In the former instance, other ethnichacia1 groups are
ignored; in the latter, such inclusive categorizations assume etiological and
historical/cultural invariance between groups.
Clearly, one of the first places for feminists to start is to target women of
color for greater research. Available data indicate that there are significant
differences between black and white female crime rates (Ageton, 1983;
Chilton and Datesman, 1987; Hindelang, 1981; Laub and McDermott, 1985;
Mann, 1987; Young, 1980). Simpson (1988), Miller (1985), and Lewis (1981)
argue that the unique structural and cultural positioning of black women produces
complex cultural typescripts that exert push-pull pressures for crime,
pressures that may not exist for white women.
Miller’s (1985: 177-178) ethnography of lower-class deviant networks
describes how certain types of male and female criminality (e.g., hustling,
pimping, and other instrumental crimes) are interdependent in minority communities.
Female crime also appears to have a group-directed and -enacted
dimension (see Young, 1980). The collective nature of such minority offending
may stem from the fact that it emerges, in part, from the integrated and
extended domestic networks of underclass blacks (Miller, 1985) and from
joint participation in gang activities (Campbell, 1984).
These observations do not imply, however, that patriarchy is absent from
these communities. Male dominance and control are reproduced within
interpersonal relationships (not necessarily familial) and embodied in informal
organizations, like gangs (Campbell, 1984) and state social service agencies.
Some female offending can be interpreted as challenging patriarchal
control and asserting independence (Campbell, 1984: 135); much can be
attributed to both economic necessity and the pull and excitement of street
life (Campbell, 1984; Miller, 1985). Female participation in violent crime
may stem from abusive relationships between men and women (Browne,
1987; Mann, 1987) and/or the frustration, alienation, and anger that are associated
with racial and class oppression (Simpson, 1988).
Research by Hill and Suva1 (1988) suggests that the causes of crime may
differ for black and white women, which raises questions about whether current
theories of female crime, including feminist perspectives, are whitefemale
centered. Given the paucity of data on how gender structures relationships
within minority communities and families, it is impossible to say.
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 619
More quantitative research is needed on minority groups other than blacks
(e.g., Chicanos and other Hispanics, Asians, Native Americans) to establish a
better knowledge base, but qualitative studies that probe culture and subjective
differences between women of color and whites are also essential (Mullins,
1986). Feminist criminologists are guilty of the “add race and stir”
shortsightedness that pervades feminist thinking. We would do well to heed
Spelman’s (1988:166) reminder of how to understand and approach differences
among women:
If we assume there are differences among women, but at the same time
they are all the same as women, and if we assume the woman part is
what we know from looking at the case of white middle-class women,
then we appear to be talking only about white middle-class women. This
is how white middle-class privilege is maintained even as we purport to
recognize the importance of women’s differences.
ELITE CRIME
In 1977, Harris admonished criminologists for their failure to use “the sex
variable” as the empirical building block for all theories of criminal deviance.
Apparently (though not surprisingly) this was interpreted to apply only to
street crime. The entire area of white-collar, corporate, and organizational
crime has not been examined from a feminist perspective.
Officially, women are underrepresented in white-collar crime data although
recent Bureau of Justice Sfatistics (1987) data suggest that women have made
inroads into this formerly male domain. Similar claims are made regarding
female penetration of the upper reaches of organized crime (Simpson, 1987).
Yet, Daly (1988) finds neither the crime types nor the offenders themselves to
be particularly elite.
Much of our information on female participation in organized crime is
anecdotal, derived from the nonsystematic observations of male crime participants.
Consequently, there has been little systematic research on women’s
penetration of and mobility within illicit markets. The official data on corporate
and other white-collar offending are equally problematic (see Reiss and
Biderman, 1980). Given that both the data and interpretation/theory in
these areas are suspect, feminist researchers must first develop an empirical
base with which to answer the following types of questions. Is elite crime a
male domain (Steffensmeier, 1983)? What are the motivations and characteristics
of women who do participate (Daly, 1988; Zietz, 1981)? How are they
similar and different from male offenders (P. Adler, 1985; Block, 1977; Simpson,
1987)? What explains the official increase in female participation in
white-collar offenses?
At this point, feminists have barely scratched the surface of the elite crime
620 SIMPSON
area. Daly (1988) is providing some direction, but much more needs to be
done.
DETERRENCE
Gender confounds the anticipated relationship between objective sanction
risks and criminal activity, that is, given that female sanction risks are low,
women should have high rates of law breaking. Yet, as virtually all measures
of crime document, the exact opposite is true. This empirical relationship has
left deterrence theorists scrambling to make sense of the inconsistency.
Richards and Tittle (1 98 1 : 183-1 85) argue that there are at least five lines of
reasoning that would predict that women perceive higher levels of risk than
do men. Using measures derived from these hypotheses, they find two variables,
stakes in conformity and perceptions of visibility, to be highly associated
with gender differences in perceived chances of arrest:
Women may think that legal sanction is relatively certain because they
are more likely to think of themselves as subject to surveillance and general
social sanctions than are men. Their greater relative stakes in conformity
may make deviance more threatening for them, and lead to high
sanction risk estimates (p. 196).
The social control literature, in general, characterizes female conformity in a
stereotypical manner. Conforming females are seen as passive, compliant,
and dependent. Instead, Naffine (1988: 13 1) suggests that the conforming
women be seen as “involved and engrossed in conventional life. But . . . also
actively concerned about the effects of her behavior on her loved ones, particularly
emotionally and financially dependent children.” (Naffine is especially
critical of Hagan et al., 1979, 1985, 1987.)
Naffine’s image of conformity is partially influenced by Gilligan’s (1982)
work in moral development theory. Gilligan’s research discovers that men
and women use “a different voice” when they talk about moral responsibility.
If the moral calculus of reasoning about crime is different between men and
women, Gilligan may have identified a new way of conceptualizing gender
differences in (1) perceived threat of sanction and (2) male-female crime rates.
According to her theory, men often make moral decisions based on an “ethic
of justice,” while women employ a model of decision making based on an
“ethic of care.” The former is a more abstract model, expressed as a set of
principles defining rights and rules (e.g., Kohlberg, 1981). In the latter, decisions
are governed by “a psychological logic of relationships, which contrasts
with the formal logic of fairness that informs the justice approach” (Gilligan,
1 9 82:73).
A woman’s decision to violate the law will depend on her definition of the
moral domain (i.e., how will my act affect those around me, those who count
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 62 1
on me). It is not surprising that in some deterrence studies (Finley and Grasmick,
1985) women score significantly higher than men on measures of internalized
guilt. Because women are responsible for the care of relationships,
any act that may result in their removal from that role is apt to produce a
tremendous sense of guilt. Guilt may be negated if the needs of the family
(for food or other valued items) outweigh the “immorality” of breaking the
law to obtain them or if others are available to take on the responsibilities of
care.
Gilligan’s theory can be used to explain why most women do not violate
the law and why they score higher on most measures of deterrence. It can
also explain class and race differences in female crime rates. Lower-class and
minority women are more apt to find themselves in situations that require a
renegotiation of the moral domain and, given their kinship networks, they
have a greater chance of finding care substitutes (Miller, 1985). Not surprisingly,
Finley and Grasmick (1985) report that blacks score lower on certainty
and severity of guilt than their white counterparts.
Some critics suggest that Gilligan’s findings are biased (she interviewed
mostly middle-class students) or that they may be a function of subordinate
female social position, not real differences in ethical philosophies (Tronto,
n.d.). These are important criticisms that must be addressed before we proceed
too enthusiastically. Gilligan’s conceptualization of differences in gender-
based moral reasoning, however, are an important contribution and
warrant further research.
CONCLUSION
Feminist criminology has changed dramatically since Klein (1 973) and
Smart (1976) first called attention to it. Replicating the same political and
analytical development as the broader feminist movement, feminist contributions
to the study of crime and justice began with more liberal approaches
and have recently been giving way to more radical critiques. Liberal feminist
dominance rests, in part, in ideological coherence-these approaches correspond
closely with the ideas and beliefs embodied in most capitalist democracies.
Thus, liberalism in any form is less threatening and more acceptable
than a feminism that questions white, male, and/or capitalist privilege. 1 1
Additionally, liberal feminists speak in the same voice as a majority of social
scientists, that is, they are rational, objective, and (typically) quantitative.
Consequently, their data and interpretations carry more weight within the
scientific community and among their peers.
11. Stacey and Thorne (1985:308) argue that more radical feminist thinking has been
marginalized-ghettoized within Marxist sociology, which ensures that feminist thinking
has less of a chance to influence mainstream sociological paradigms and research.
622 SIMPSON
Though 1iberaVquantitative approaches offer important insights into gender
as a “variable” problem (Stacey and Thorne, 1985), criminologists need
to be more ecumenical in studying gendered society. If we emphasize qualitative
(e.g., Campbell, 1984; Carlen, 1986; Eaton, 1986; Miller, 1985), historical
(Gordon, 1988; Freedman, 1981; Rafter, 1985), and subjectivist (Stacey and
Thorne, 1985) approaches in addition to quantitative, the detail and texture
of how crime and justice are gendered will lead to richer theory and better
criminology.
There are areas in criminology into which feminists have only marginally
ventured or in which their contributions have been of little consequence. In
their review of feminist criminology, Daly and Chesney-Lind (1988512-5 13)
discuss the problems that feminists have had building and developing theories
of female crime. It is not coincidental that the areas targeted for further
research in this paper (e.g., race and crime, elite crime, and deterrence) all
focus on this problematic area. Until we can better deal with the empirical
complexities of criminal offending, it will be too easy for our critics to dismiss
feminist contributions to the study of crime as facile, rhetorical, and/or
atheoretical.
REFERENCES
Adler, Freda
1975 Sisters in Crime: The Rise of the New Female Criminal. New York:
1981
McGraw-Hill.
The Incidence of Female Criminality in the Contemporary World. New
York: New York University Press.
Wheeling and Dealing: An Ethnography of an Upper-Level Drug Dealing
and Smuggling Community. New York: Columbia University Press.
The dynamics of female delinquency, 1976-1980. Criminology 2 1:555-584.
Victim precipitated forcible rape. Journal of Criminal Law, Criminology,
and Police Science 58:493-502.
Adler, Patricia
1985
Ageton, Suzanne S.
Amir, Menachem
1983
1967
Atkinson, Ti-Grace
1974 Radical Feminism and Love. In Amazon Odyssey. New York: Links
Books.
Women’s liberation and increases in minor, major, and occupational offenses.
Criminology 20:407430.
Austin, Roy L.
1982
Barry, Kathleen
Beauvoir, Simone de
1979 Female Sexual Slavery. New York: Avon Books.
1960 The Second Sex. London: Four Square Books.
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 623
Bem, Sandra
1974 The measurement of psychological androgyny. Journal of Consulting and
Clinical Psychology 42:155-162.
Charge reduction: An intermediary stage in the process of labelling criminal
defendants. Social Forces 56:362-384.
Bernstein, Ilene Nagel, Edward Kick, Jan Leung, and Barbara Schulz
1977
Bishop, Cecil
Black, Donald
1931 Women and Crime. London: Chato and Windus Press.
1980 On the Manners and Customs of the Police. New York: Academic Press.
Block, Alan
1977 Aw! Your mother’s in the mafia: Women criminals in progressive New
York. Contemporary Crises 15-22,
Box, Steven
Box, Steven and Chris Hale
1983 Power, Crime, and Mystification. London: Tavistock.
1984 Liberation/emancipation, economic marginalization, or less chivalry: The
relevance of three theoretical arguments to female crime patterns in England
and Wales, 195 1-1980. Criminology 22:473497.
Sexism, Racism and Oppression. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Brittan, Arthur and Mary Maynard
Browne, Angela
Brownmiller, Susan
1984
1987 When Battered Women Kill. New York: Free Press.
1975 Against Our Will: Men, Women, and Rape. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Burkhart, Kathryn Watterson
Bureau of Justice Statistics
1973 Women in Prison. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday.
1987 Special Report: White-collar Crime. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Department
of Justice.
Campbell, Anne
1984 The Girls in the Gang: A Report from New York City. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Women’s Imprisonment: A Study in Social Contol. London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Carlen, Pat
1983
Chapman, Jane Roberts and Margaret Gates (eds.)
Chesney-Lind, Meda
1978 The Victimization of Women. Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage.
1973
1980
Judicial enforcement of the female sex role. Issues in Criminology 8:51-69.
Rediscovering Lilith: Misogyny and the “new” female criminal. In Curt
Taylor Griffiths and Margot Nance (eds.), The Female Offender. Criminology
Research Centre. Burnaby, B.C.: Simon Fraser University.
1986 Women and crime: The female offender. Signs 12:78-96.
624 SIMPSON
Chilton, Roland and Susan K. Datesman
1987 Gender, race, and crime: An analysis of urban arrest trends, 1960-1980.
Gender and Society 1:152-171.
Cloward, Richard A. and Frances Fox Piven
1979 Hidden protest: The channeling of female innovation and resistance. Signs
4:651-669.
Daly, Kathleen
1987a
1987b
1988
Discrimination in the criminal courts: Family, gender and the problem of
equal treatment. Social Forces 66:152-175.
Structure and practice of familial-based justice in a criminal court. Law and
Society Review 21:267-290.
Gender and varieties of white-collar crime. Revised version of a paper
presented at the annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology,
Atlanta.
Neither conflict nor labeling nor paternalism will suffice: Intersections of
race, ethnicity, gender, and family in criminal court decisions. Crime and
Delinquency 35:136-168.
Rethinking judicial paternalism: Gender, work-family relations, and sentencing.
Gender and Society 3:9-36.
Feminism and criminology. Justice Quarterly 5: 497-538.
1980 Women, Crime, and Justice. New York: Oxford University Press.
1989a
1989b
Daly, Kathleen and Meda Chesney-Lind.
1988
Datesman, Susan K. and Frank R. Scarpitti (eds.)
Davis, Angela
1981 Women, Race, and Class. New York: Random House.
Dobash, R. Emerson and Russell Dobash
1979 Violence Against Wives: A Case Against the Patriarchy. New York: Free
Press.
Dworkin, Andrea
1981 Pornography: Men Possessing Women. New York: Perigee Books.
Eaton, Mary
1986 Justice for Women? Family, Court, and Social Control. Philadelphia: Open
1987
University Press.
The question of bail: Magistrates’ responses to applications for bail on
behalf of men and women defendants. In Pat Carlen and Anne Worrall
(eds.), Gender, Crime and Justice. Philadelphia: Open University Press.
Women on Trial: A Study of the Female Suspect, Defendant, and Offender
in the Criminal Law and Criminal Justice System. Manchester, N.H.:
Manchester University Press.
Edwards, Susan M.
1985
Eisenstein, Zillah
1979
1981 The Radical Future of Liberal Feminism. New York: Monthly Review
Capitalist Patriarchy and the Case for Socialist Feminism. New York:
Monthly Review Press.
Press.
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 625
Elliott, Delbert and Suzanne S. Ageton
1980 Reconciling race and class differences in self-reported and official estimates
of delinquency. American Sociological Review 45:95-110.
Sex, sentencing and reconviction. British Journal of Criminology
Farrington, David and Allison Morris
1983
23~229-248.
Finkelhor, David
Finley, Nancy J. and Harold G. Grasmick
Firestone, Shulamith
Bantam.
Their Sisters’ Keepers: Women’s Prison Reform in America, 1830-1930.
Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
An assessment of the black female prisoner in the South. Signs 3:483488.
The incarcerated black female: The case of social double jeopardy. Journal
of Black Studies 8:321-335.
Gender differences in delinquency quantity and quality. In Lee H. Bowker
(ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan.
In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
The economics of female criminality: An analysis of police blotters
1890-1975. In Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women and Crime in America. New
York: Macmillian.
Five Hundred Delinquent Women. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
The New Female Criminal: Empirical Reality or Social Myth? New York:
Praeger.
Heroes of Their Own Lives: The Politics and History of Family Violence.
New York: Penguin.
1979 Sexually Victimized Children. New York: Free Press.
1985
1970 The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revolution. New York:
Gender roles and social control. Sociological Spectrum 5:3 17-330.
Freedman, Estelle
1981
French, Laurence
1977
1978
Freyerhern, William
1981
Gilligan, Carol
1982
Giordano, Peggy, Sandra Kerbel, and Sandra Dudley
1981
Glueck, Sheldon and Eleanor Glueck
Gora, Joann Gennaro
1934
1982
Gordon, Linda
1988
Greer, Germaine
Griffin, Susan
Haft, Marilyn G.
1970 The Female Eunuch. New York: McGraw-Hill.
1979 Rape: The Power of Consciousness. San Francisco: Harper & Row.
Women in prison: Discriminary practices and some legal solutions. In
Susan Datesman and Frank R. Scarpitti (eds.), Women, Crime, and Justice.
New York: Oxford University Press.
1980
SIMPSON
Hagan, John, A.R. Gillis, and John Simpson
1985 The class structure of gender and delinquency: Toward a power control
theory of common delinquent behavior. American Journal of Sociology
90:1151-1l78.
Hagan, John, John Simpson, and A.R. Gillis
The sexual stratification of social control: A gender-based perspective on
crime and delinquency. British Journal of Sociology 30:25-38.
Class in the household: A power-control theory of gender and delinquency.
American Journal of Sociology 92:788-816.
Violence and the Social Control of Women. Feminist Issues 1:2946.
1979
1987
Hanmer, Jalna
Harris, Anthony R.
1981
1977 Sex and theories of deviance: Toward a functional theory of deviant typescripts.
American Sociological Review 42:3-16.
The unhappy marriage of Marxism and feminism: Toward a more
progressive union. Capital and Class (Summer): 1-1 3.
Women in constraints. In S.K. Mukherjee and Jocelynne A. Scutt (eds.),
Women and Crime. Sydney: Australian Institute of Criminology with Allen
and Unwin.
Hartman, Heida
1979
Hartz-Karp, Janette
1981
Heide, Wilma Scott
1974 Feminism and the “fallen woman”. Criminal Justice and Behavior
1~369-373.
Heidensohn, Frances
1968
1985 Women and Crime. London: Macmillan.
The deviance of women: A critique and an enquiry. British Journal of
Sociology 19:160-175.
Hill, Gary D. and Elizabeth M. Suva1
1988 Women, race, and crime. A revised version of a paper presented at the
annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology, Chicago.
Hindelang, Michael
1981 Variations in sex-race-age-specific incidence rates of offending. American
Sociological Review 46:461-474.
Feminism: A movement to end sexist oppression. In Anne Phillips (ed.),
Feminism and Equality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
The value of quantitative methodology for feminist research. In Gloria
Bowles and Renate Duelli Klein (eds.), Theories of Women’s Studies.
Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
The incompatible menage a trois: Marxism, feminism, and racism. In Lydia
Sargent (ed.), Women and Revolution. Boston: South End Press.
White promotion, black survival. In Gloria I. Joseph and Jill Lewis (eds.),
Common Differences: Conflicts in Black and White Feminist Perspectives.
Boston: South End Press.
Hooks, Bell
1987
Jayarate, Toby Epstein
1983
Joseph, Gloria I.
1981a
1981b
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 627
Joseph, Gloria I. and Jill Lewis (eds.)
Common Differences: Conflicts in Black and White Feminist Perspectives.
Boston: South End Press.
198 1
Keller, Evelyn Fox
1982 Feminism and science. In Nannerl 0. Keohane, Michele Z. Rosaldo, and
Barbara C. Gelpi (eds.), Feminist Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Klein, Dorie
1973
1981
The etiology of female crime: A review of the literature. Issues in
Criminology 8:3-29.
Violence against women: Some considerations regarding its causes and its
elimination. Crime and Delinquency 27:64-80.
The Philosophy of Moral Development. San Francisco: Harper & Row.
1982 Respectable women and the law. The Sociological Quarterly 23:221-234.
1984
Kohlberg, Lawrence
Kruttschnitt, Candace
1981
Sex and criminal court dispositions: The unresolved controversy. Journal of
Research in Crime and Delinquency 21 :213-232.
Kuhn, Thomas
1970 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Laub, John and M. Joan McDermott
An analysis of serious crime by young black women. Criminology 23:81-98.
Black women offenders and criminal justice: Some theoretical considerations.
In Marguerite Warren (ed.), Comparing Female and Male Offenders.
Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage.
1985
Lewis, Diane
198 1
MacKinnon, Catherine A.
1979 The Sexual Harassment of Working Women. New Haven: Yale University
Press.
1982 Feminism, Marxism, method, and the state: An agenda for theory. In
Nannerl 0. Keohane, Michele Z. Rosaldo, and Barbara C. Gelpi (eds.),
Feminist Theory, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Female Crime and Delinquency. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.
Black female homicide in the United States. Paper presented at the
Conference on Black Homicide and Public Health, Baltimore.
Mann, Coramae Richey
1984
1987
Martin, Del
Miles, Maria
1976 Battered Wives. New York: Pocket Books/Simon & Schuster.
1983 Toward a methodology for feminist research. In Gloria Bowles and Renate
Duelli Klein (eds.), Theories of Women’s Studies. Boston: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Street Woman. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Miller, Eleanor M.
1985
628 SIMPSON
Millett, Kate
Mitchell, Juliet
197 1 Sexual Politics. London: Rupert Hart-Davis.
1971 Woman’s Estate. New York: Random House.
Moyer, Imogene L.
1985 The Changing Roles of Women in the Criminal Justice System: Offenders,
Victims, and Professionals. Prospect Heights, Ill.: Waveland Press.
Police processing of female offenders. In Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women and
Crime in America. New York: Macmillan.
Moyer, Imogene L. and Garland F. White
1981
Mukherjee, S.K. and R.W. Fitzgerald
1981 The myth of rising female crime. In S.K. Mukherjee and Jocelynne A. Scutt
(eds.), Women and Crime. Sydney: Australian Institute of Criminology
with Allen and Unwin.
Mukherjee, S.K. and Jocelynne A. Scutt (eds.)
1981 Women and Crime. Sydney: Australian Institute of Criminology with Allen
and Unwin.
Naffine, Ngaire
1988 Female Crime: The Construction of Women in Criminology. Boston: Allen
and Unwin.
Nagel, Ilene H.
1981 Sex differences in the processing of criminal defendants. In A. Morris and
L. Gelsthorpe (eds.), Women and Crime. Cambridge: Cambridge Institute
of Criminology.
The legal/extra-legal controversy: Judicial decisions in pretrial release. Law
and Society Review 17:481-515.
Double standard of American justice. Society 9:18-25, 62-63.
1983
Nagel, Stuart and Lenore J. Weitzman
Oakley, Ann
Pagelow, Mildred
1972
1981 Subject Women. New York: Pantheon.
1981 Sex roles, power, and woman battering. In Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women
and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan.
Pateman, Carol
1987 Feminist critiques of the public/private dichotomy. In Anne Phillips (ed.),
Feminism and Equality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
1987 Feminism and Equality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Phillips, Anne (ed.)
Plenska, Danuta
1980 Women’s criminality in Poland. In Curt Taylor Griffiths and Margot Nance
(eds.), The Female Offender. Criminology Research Centre. Burnaby, B.C.:
Simon Fraser University.
Rafter, Nicole Hahn
1985 Partial Justice: Women in State Prisons, 1800-1935. Boston: Northeastern
University Press.
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 629
Rafter, Nicole Hahn and Elena Natalizaia
198 1 Marxist feminist: Implications for criminal justice. Crime and Delinquency
27:81-98.
Rasche, Christine
1974 The female offender as an object of criminological research. Criminal Justice
and Behavior 1:301-320.
Experimental analysis: A contribution to feminist research. In Gloria
Bowles and Renate Duelli Klein (eds.), Theories of Women’s Studies.
Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Reinhartz, Shulamit
1983
Reiss, Albert J., Jr. and Albert P. Biderman
1980 Data Sources on White-collar Law-Breaking. National Institute of Justice.
Washington, D.C.: U.S. Department of Justice.
Compulsory heterosexual and lesbian existence. Signs 5:63 1-660.
Gender and perceived chances of arrest. Social Forces 59:1182-I 199.
The fear of rape: A study in social control. Journal of Social Issues
Rich, Adrienne
Richards, Pamela and Charles R. Tittle
Riger, Stephanie and Margaret T. Gordon
1980
1981
1981
37:71-92.
Sanday, Peggy Reeves
1981 The socio-cultural context of rape: A cross-cultural study. The Journal of
Social Issues 37:5-27.
The crime of precocious sexuality: Female juvenile delinquency in the
progressive era. Harvard Educational Review 48:65-94.
Women in elite deviance: A grounded theory. Paper presented at the
annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology, Montreal.
Caste, class, and crime: Violence and the disenfranchised black female.
Revised version of a paper presented at the annual meeting of the American
Society of Criminology, Chicago.
Schlossman, Steven and Stephanie Wallach
1978
Simpson, Sally S.
1987
1988
Simon, Rita
Smart, Carol
1975 Women and Crime. Lexington, Mass.: D.C. Heath.
1976 Women, Crime and Criminology: A Feminist Critique. London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul.
Equity and discretionary justice: The influence of race on police arrest
decisions. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 75:234-249.
1988 Inessential Woman: Problems of Exclusion in Feminist Thought. Boston:
Smith, Douglas, Christy Visher, and Laura Davidson
1984
Spelman, Elizabeth V.
Beacon.
The effect of race on sentencing: A re-examination of an unsettled question.
Law and Society Review 16:71-88.
Spohn, Cassia, John Gruhl, and Susan Welch
1982
630 SIMPSON
Stacey, Judith and Barrie Thorne
Stanko, Elizabeth A.
1985 The missing feminist revolution in sociology. Social Problems 32:301-3 16.
1985 Intimate Intrusions: Women’s Experience of Male Violence. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Crime and the contemporary woman: An analysis of changing levels of
female property crime, 1960-75. Social Forces 57:566584.
Patterns of female property crime, 1960-1975: A postscript. In Lee H.
Bowker (ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan.
Organization properties and sex-segregation in the underworld: Building a
sociological theory of sex differences in crime. Social Forces 61:1010-1043.
Sex differences in urban arrest patterns, 1934-79. Social Problems 29:37-50.
Behind Closed Doors: Violence in the American Family. Garden City,
N.Y.: Anchor/Doubleday.
A “torrent of abuse”: Crimes of violence between working-class men and
women in London, 1840-1875. Journal of Social History 11:328-345.
Steffensmeier, Darrell J.
1978
1981
1983
Steffensmeier, Darrell J. and Michael J. Cobb
Straus, Murray A., Richard J. Gelles, and Suzanne K. Steinmetz
1981
1980
Tomes, Nancy
1978
Tracy, Paul E., Marvin E. Wolfgang, and Robert M. Figlio
Tronto, Joan C.
In press Delinquent Careers in Two Birth Cohorts. New York: Plenum Publishing.
n.d. “Women’s morality”: Beyond gender difference to a theory of care.
Unpublished paper, Hunter College of the City University of New York.
Cited in Gloria I. Joseph and Jill Lewis (eds.), Common Differences:
Conflicts in Black and White Feminist Perspectives. Boston: South End
Press.
Truth, Sojourner
1851
Visher, Christy
1983 Gender, police arrest decisions, and notions of chivalry. Criminology
2 15-28,
Wellman, David
1977 Portraits of White Racism. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, James Q. and Richard J. Herrnstein
Wilson, Nanci Koser
1985 Crime and Human Nature. New York: Simon & Schuster.
1985 Witches, hookers, and others: Societal response to women criminals and
victims. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Society of
Criminology, San Diego.
The victim in a forcible rape case: A feminist view. In Lee H. Bowker
(ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan.
Wood, Pamela
1981
Young, Vernetta D.
1980 Women, race, and crime. Criminology 18:2&34.
FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 63 1
Zietz, Dorothy
1981 Women Who Embezzle or Defraud: A Study of Convicted Felons. New
York: Praeger.
Sally S. Simpson is an Assistant Professor of Criminal Justice and Criminology at the
University of Maryland, College Park. In addition to her interest in issues of gender and
crime, she is currently involved in studies of organizational change and its effects on the
ethical dimensions of decision-making.